Axiom Of Determinacy
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In mathematics, the axiom of determinacy (abbreviated as AD) is a possible axiom for
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly conce ...
introduced by
Jan Mycielski Jan Mycielski (born February 7, 1932 in Wiśniowa, Podkarpackie Voivodeship, Poland)Curriculum vitae
from ...
and
Hugo Steinhaus Hugo Dyonizy Steinhaus ( ; ; January 14, 1887 – February 25, 1972) was a Polish mathematician and educator. Steinhaus obtained his PhD under David Hilbert at Göttingen University in 1911 and later became a professor at the Jan Kazimierz Un ...
in 1962. It refers to certain two-person
topological game In mathematics, a topological game is an infinite game of perfect information played between two players on a topological space. Players choose objects with topological properties such as points, open sets, closed sets and open coverings. Time ...
s of length ω. AD states that every game of a certain type is determined; that is, one of the two players has a
winning strategy Determinacy is a subfield of set theory, a branch of mathematics, that examines the conditions under which one or the other player of a game has a winning strategy, and the consequences of the existence of such strategies. Alternatively and sim ...
. Steinhaus and Mycielski's motivation for AD was its interesting consequences, and suggested that AD could be true in the smallest natural model
L(R) In set theory, L(R) (pronounced L of R) is the smallest transitive inner model of ZF containing all the ordinals and all the reals. Construction It can be constructed in a manner analogous to the construction of L (that is, Gödel's constructi ...
of a set theory, which accepts only a weak form of the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
(AC) but contains all
real Real may refer to: Currencies * Brazilian real (R$) * Central American Republic real * Mexican real * Portuguese real * Spanish real * Spanish colonial real Music Albums * ''Real'' (L'Arc-en-Ciel album) (2000) * ''Real'' (Bright album) (2010) ...
and all ordinal numbers. Some consequences of AD followed from theorems proved earlier by
Stefan Banach Stefan Banach ( ; 30 March 1892 – 31 August 1945) was a Polish mathematician who is generally considered one of the 20th century's most important and influential mathematicians. He was the founder of modern functional analysis, and an origina ...
and
Stanisław Mazur Stanisław Mieczysław Mazur (1 January 1905, Lwów – 5 November 1981, Warsaw) was a Polish mathematician and a member of the Polish Academy of Sciences. Mazur made important contributions to geometrical methods in linear and nonlinear functio ...
, and Morton Davis. Mycielski and
Stanisław Świerczkowski Stanisław (Stash) Świerczkowski (16 July 1932 – 30 September 2015) was a Polish mathematician famous for his solutions to two iconic problems posed by Hugo Steinhaus: the three-gap theorem and the Non-Tetratorus Theorem. Early life and ed ...
contributed another one: AD implies that all sets of
real number In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a ''continuous'' one-dimensional quantity such as a distance, duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that values can have arbitrarily small variations. Every ...
s are
Lebesgue measurable In measure theory, a branch of mathematics, the Lebesgue measure, named after French mathematician Henri Lebesgue, is the standard way of assigning a measure to subsets of ''n''-dimensional Euclidean space. For ''n'' = 1, 2, or 3, it coincides wit ...
. Later
Donald A. Martin Donald Anthony Martin (born December 24, 1940), also known as Tony Martin, is an American set theorist and philosopher of mathematics at UCLA, where he is an emeritus professor of mathematics and philosophy. Education and career Martin rece ...
and others proved more important consequences, especially in descriptive set theory. In 1988, John R. Steel and
W. Hugh Woodin William Hugh Woodin (born April 23, 1955) is an American mathematician and set theorist at Harvard University. He has made many notable contributions to the theory of inner models and determinacy. A type of large cardinals, the Woodin cardinals, ...
concluded a long line of research. Assuming the existence of some
uncountable In mathematics, an uncountable set (or uncountably infinite set) is an infinite set that contains too many elements to be countable. The uncountability of a set is closely related to its cardinal number: a set is uncountable if its cardinal num ...
cardinal number In mathematics, cardinal numbers, or cardinals for short, are a generalization of the natural numbers used to measure the cardinality (size) of sets. The cardinality of a finite set is a natural number: the number of elements in the set. T ...
s analogous to \alef_0, they proved the original conjecture of Mycielski and Steinhaus that AD is true in L(R).


Types of game that are determined

The axiom of determinacy refers to games of the following specific form: Consider a subset ''A'' of the
Baire space In mathematics, a topological space X is said to be a Baire space if countable unions of closed sets with empty interior also have empty interior. According to the Baire category theorem, compact Hausdorff spaces and complete metric spaces are e ...
''ωω'' of all
infinite sequence In mathematics, a sequence is an enumerated collection of objects in which repetitions are allowed and order matters. Like a set, it contains members (also called ''elements'', or ''terms''). The number of elements (possibly infinite) is called t ...
s of
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country"). Numbers used for counting are called ''cardinal ...
s. Two players, I and II, alternately pick natural numbers :''n''0, ''n''1, ''n''2, ''n''3, ... After infinitely many moves, a sequence (n_i)_ is generated. Player I wins the game if and only if the sequence generated is an element of ''A''. The axiom of determinacy is the statement that all such games are determined. Not all games require the axiom of determinacy to prove them determined. If the set ''A'' is
clopen In topology, a clopen set (a portmanteau of closed-open set) in a topological space is a set which is both open and closed. That this is possible may seem counter-intuitive, as the common meanings of and are antonyms, but their mathematical de ...
, the game is essentially a finite game, and is therefore determined. Similarly, if ''A'' is a closed set, then the game is determined. It was shown in 1975 by
Donald A. Martin Donald Anthony Martin (born December 24, 1940), also known as Tony Martin, is an American set theorist and philosopher of mathematics at UCLA, where he is an emeritus professor of mathematics and philosophy. Education and career Martin rece ...
that games whose winning set is a
Borel set In mathematics, a Borel set is any set in a topological space that can be formed from open sets (or, equivalently, from closed sets) through the operations of countable union, countable intersection, and relative complement. Borel sets are na ...
are determined. It follows from the existence of sufficiently large cardinals that all games with winning set a
projective set In the mathematical field of descriptive set theory, a subset A of a Polish space X is projective if it is \boldsymbol^1_n for some positive integer n. Here A is * \boldsymbol^1_1 if A is analytic * \boldsymbol^1_n if the complement of A, X\se ...
are determined (see
Projective determinacy In mathematical logic, projective determinacy is the special case of the axiom of determinacy applying only to projective sets. The axiom of projective determinacy, abbreviated PD, states that for any two-player infinite game of perfect informatio ...
), and that AD holds in
L(R) In set theory, L(R) (pronounced L of R) is the smallest transitive inner model of ZF containing all the ordinals and all the reals. Construction It can be constructed in a manner analogous to the construction of L (that is, Gödel's constructi ...
. The axiom of determinacy implies that for every subspace ''X'' of the real numbers, the
Banach–Mazur game In general topology, set theory and game theory, a Banach– Mazur game is a topological game played by two players, trying to pin down elements in a set (space). The concept of a Banach–Mazur game is closely related to the concept of Baire s ...
''BM''(''X'') is determined (and therefore that every set of reals has the
property of Baire A subset A of a topological space X has the property of Baire (Baire property, named after René-Louis Baire), or is called an almost open set, if it differs from an open set by a meager set; that is, if there is an open set U\subseteq X such th ...
).


Incompatibility of the axiom of determinacy with the axiom of choice

Under assumption of the axiom of choice, we create a counterexample to the axiom of determinacy. The set S1 of all first player strategies in an ω-game ''G'' has the same cardinality as the
continuum Continuum may refer to: * Continuum (measurement), theories or models that explain gradual transitions from one condition to another without abrupt changes Mathematics * Continuum (set theory), the real line or the corresponding cardinal number ...
. The same is true for the set S2 of all second player strategies. Let ''SG'' be the set of all possible sequences in ''G'', and A be the subset of sequences of ''SG'' that make the first player win. With the axiom of choice we can
well order In mathematics, a well-order (or well-ordering or well-order relation) on a set ''S'' is a total order on ''S'' with the property that every non-empty subset of ''S'' has a least element in this ordering. The set ''S'' together with the well-ord ...
the continuum, and we can do so in such a way that any proper initial portion has lower cardinality than the continuum. We use the obtained well ordered set J to index both S1 and S2, and construct A such that it will be a counterexample. We start with empty sets A and B. Let α \in J be the index of the strategies in S1 and S2. We need to consider all strategies S1 = of the first player and all strategies S2 = of the second player to make sure that for every strategy there is a strategy of the other player that wins against it. For every strategy of the player considered we will generate a sequence that gives the other player a win. Let t be the time whose axis has length ℵ0 and which is used during each game sequence. We create the counterexample A by
transfinite recursion Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for a ...
on α: # Consider the strategy s1(α) of the first player. #Apply this strategy on an ω-game, generating (together with the first player's strategy s1(α)) a sequence , which does not belong to A. This is possible, because the number of choices for has the same cardinality as the continuum, which is larger than the cardinality of the proper initial portion of J. #Add this sequence to B (if it is not already in B), to indicate that s1(α) loses (on ). #Consider the strategy s2(α) of the second player. #Apply this strategy on an ω-game, generating (together with the second player's strategy s2(α)) a sequence , which does not belong to B. This is possible, because the number of choices for has the same cardinality as the continuum, which is larger than the cardinality of the proper initial portion of J. #Add this sequence to A (if it is not already in A), to indicate that s2(α) loses (on ). #Process all possible strategies of S1 and S2 with
transfinite induction Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for ...
on α. For all sequences that are not in A or B after that, decide arbitrarily whether they belong to A or to B. So B is the complement of A. Once this has been done, prepare for an ω-game ''G''. If you give me a strategy s1 of the first player, then there is an α \in J such that s1 = s1(α), and we constructed A such that s1(α) fails (on certain choices of the second player). Hence s1 fails. Similarly, any other strategy of either player fails. Hence the axiom of determinacy and the axiom of choice are incompatible.


Infinitary logic and the axiom of determinacy

Many different versions of
infinitary logic An infinitary logic is a logic that allows infinitely long statements and/or infinitely long proofs. Some infinitary logics may have different properties from those of standard first-order logic. In particular, infinitary logics may fail to be co ...
were proposed in the late 20th century. One reason that has been given for believing in the axiom of determinacy is that it can be written as follows (in a version of infinite logic): \forall G \subseteq Seq(S): \forall a \in S: \exists a' \in S: \forall b \in S: \exists b' \in S: \forall c \in S: \exists c' \in S ... : (a,a',b,b',c,c'...) \in G OR \exists a \in S: \forall a' \in S: \exists b \in S: \forall b' \in S: \exists c \in S: \forall c' \in S ... :(a,a',b,b',c,c'...) \notin G Note: Seq(''S'') is the set of all \omega-sequences of ''S''. The sentences here are infinitely long with a countably infinite list of quantifiers where the ellipses appear.


Large cardinals and the axiom of determinacy

The consistency of the axiom of determinacy is closely related to the question of the consistency of large cardinal axioms. By a theorem of Woodin, the consistency of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without choice (ZF) together with the axiom of determinacy is equivalent to the consistency of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with choice (ZFC) together with the existence of infinitely many
Woodin cardinal In set theory, a Woodin cardinal (named for W. Hugh Woodin) is a cardinal number \lambda such that for all functions :f : \lambda \to \lambda there exists a cardinal \kappa < \lambda with : \ \subseteq \kappa and an
s. Since Woodin cardinals are strongly inaccessible, if AD is consistent, then so are an infinity of inaccessible cardinals. Moreover, if to the hypothesis of an infinite set of Woodin cardinals is added the existence of a
measurable cardinal In mathematics, a measurable cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number. In order to define the concept, one introduces a two-valued measure on a cardinal , or more generally on any set. For a cardinal , it can be described as a subdivisi ...
larger than all of them, a very strong theory of
Lebesgue measurable In measure theory, a branch of mathematics, the Lebesgue measure, named after French mathematician Henri Lebesgue, is the standard way of assigning a measure to subsets of ''n''-dimensional Euclidean space. For ''n'' = 1, 2, or 3, it coincides wit ...
sets of reals emerges, as it is then provable that the axiom of determinacy is true in
L(R) In set theory, L(R) (pronounced L of R) is the smallest transitive inner model of ZF containing all the ordinals and all the reals. Construction It can be constructed in a manner analogous to the construction of L (that is, Gödel's constructi ...
, and therefore that ''every'' set of real numbers in L(R) is determined.


See also

*
Axiom of real determinacy In mathematics, the axiom of real determinacy (abbreviated as ADR) is an axiom in set theory. It states the following: The axiom of real determinacy is a stronger version of the axiom of determinacy (AD), which makes the same statement about gam ...
(ADR) * Borel determinacy theorem * Martin measure *
Topological game In mathematics, a topological game is an infinite game of perfect information played between two players on a topological space. Players choose objects with topological properties such as points, open sets, closed sets and open coverings. Time ...


References

* * * * * * *


Further reading

* Philipp Rohde, ''On Extensions of the Axiom of Determinacy'', Thesis, Department of Mathematics, University of Bonn, Germany, 2001 * Telgársky, R.J.br>''Topological Games: On the 50th Anniversary of the Banach-Mazur Game''
Rocky Mountain J. Math. 17 (1987), pp. 227–276. (3.19 MB)
"Large Cardinals and Determinacy"
at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy {{Set theory Axioms of set theory Determinacy Large cardinals